CBT: A Philosophical Critique
A preliminary draft of a chapter to appear in the forthcoming Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry.
CBT: A Philosophical Appraisal
Abstract
Cognitive
Behaviour Therapy (CBT) theorists propose that disturbances in the content of,
or in our relationship with, our cognitions often underlie and maintain
emotional disturbance. Accordingly the cognitive addition to behavioural
therapy typically consists in the collaborative pinpointing and challenge of,
or encouragement of disidentification from, these cognitions by the therapist
and the patient. With the right group of problems, patients and therapists, the
practice of CBT is well known to possess therapeutic efficacy. This chapter
however primarily considers the theory rather than the therapy of CBT; in
particular it looks at the central significance it gives to cognition in healthy and disturbed emotional
function. It suggests that if ‘cognition’ is used to mean our belief and thought, then CBT theory
provides an implausible model of much emotional distress. If, on the other
hand, ‘cognition’ refers to the processing of meaning, then CBT risks losing its distinctiveness from all
therapies other than the most blandly behavioural. The chapter also suggests
that the appearance of distinct causal processes and discrete intervention
sites in CBT’s causal models of psychopathology may owe more to the formalism
of the theory than to the structure of the well or troubled mind. Finally it
questions the CBT theorist’s conception of the value of self-knowledge,
suggesting that the CBT theorist risks underplaying the value of some of the
CBT therapist’s interventions. A consequence of these critiques is that there
are reasons to doubt that CBT always works, when it does, in the manner it
tends to describe for itself.
Introduction: CBT and Philosophy
CBT is a
broad church embracing many theories, models and techniques, often now held in
conjunction with other approaches to the mind in health and distress (e.g.
compassion, mindfulness, dialectics, psychodynamics, etc.). Within this church
there are denominations that complement, but also those that compete, with one another,
both in their empirical claims and also in some of their underlying theoretical
principles (Hofmann & Asmundson, 2008).
There
are, for example, those who treat the ‘cognitive’ aspect of CBT theory as
referring specifically to maladaptive thoughts
and beliefs (e.g. Beck 1979). These
psychological states are considered distinct from perception, emotion and
behaviour. Precisely because they are seen as distinct, maladaptive cognitions
can be appealed to in non-circular causal explanations of disturbances in these
separate domains of perception, emotion and behaviour. However other theorists tie
what is ‘cognitive’ not specifically to thought and belief, but rather to the
processing of meaning (e.g. Teasdale
1997). Without assuming that meaning
is an exclusive function of thought or belief, it is instead allowed to already
belong properly to emotion, behaviour and perception. In such cases the
explanatory force of a cognitive model may derive from its identification of
the distinct structures of meaning immanent within emotion and behaviour
themselves, rather than from showing how antecedent thoughts allegedly give
rise to such disturbed emotion and behaviour.
For
these and other reasons it therefore makes little sense to offer a
philosophical critique ‘of CBT’ per se, and such a wide-ranging critique is not
attempted in this chapter. Nevertheless, underlying several popular CBT models
and treatments (henceforth ‘CBTs’) are, I shall suggest, several questionable
assumptions about the significance of cognitive factors in psychopathology. In
this chapter I add to previous critique (McEachrane, 2009; Whiting, 2007;
Robertson, 2010) in specifying four related philosophical misunderstandings
about the nature of the mind in health and distress that, I claim, can
sometimes affect CBT theorist’s understanding both of psychopathology and of
therapeutic action.
Before I
begin I think it might be helpful if I set out, using some examples, what makes
for a distinctly philosophical
critique of a particular CBT theory. Consider first the following questions
that cans be, and have been, asked of the CBTs:
For what range of difficulties, experienced by what kinds
of populations, are CBTs effective? Are CBTs more or less effective than other
therapies (e.g. psychodynamic, narrative, person-centred or drug therapies) and
practical interventions (e.g. employment and dating advice, social sport and
gardening)? How durable are the effects of CBTs compared with other treatments?
When a CBT is effective, can this be explained using typical CBT models of
psychopathology and therapeutic action, or must we account for it using ideas
taken from other cognitive, systemic or psychodynamic theories of therapeutic
action? When a CBT is found to be more or less effective than another therapy,
is this to be accounted for ideologically (i.e. because of treatment effects
due to the convictions of investigators, therapists or patients), or because of
differential treatment efficacy, or because measures are being used which are
tailored to what one but not another therapy would view as meaningful or
valuable change (e.g. is it characterological or symptomatic changes that are
being measured)?
These
are all important questions for therapists, patients, and public health policy
makers. Yet there is, I suggest, little that is distinctly philosophical about
them. Part of what it means to say this is that they are not answerable through
reflection alone, but must instead be answered by empirical investigation. The
exception is the last: reflection on what counts
as efficacy is a form of theoretical reflection on conceptual matters of
meaning, rather than discernment of empirical matters of fact. Even so such
theoretical reflection is not, in the sense in which I shall use the term here,
itself particularly philosophical. For whilst all theoretical thought concerns
itself with matters of meaning, what I have in mind by distinctly philosophical
thought instead concerns itself with whether what is said can genuinely be
understood in the way its author intends. Philosophical reflection in this
sense concerns itself not simply with meaning but more particularly with
meaningfulness; not with how, but rather with whether, something can really be
understood in the way it invites us to understand it.
In what
follows I articulate four ways in which CBTs can sometimes invite us to
construe ourselves to ourselves, both in our healthy functioning and in our
emotional distress, in ways that, it seems to me, go against what it means to
be a human subject. More particularly, I shall consider certain conceptions,
tacitly present within the psychopathological theories offered by various CBTs,
of what it is to think, feel, and meaningfully respond. My claim will be that
whilst these conceptions appear to motivate the practice of, conceptually
dovetail with the theory of, and validate the distinctive scientific
self-conception of, various CBTs, they nevertheless simply do not tally with
what reflective understanding alone reveals as the character of human mental
and emotional life. Given that such CBTs can nevertheless prove helpful to some
patients, it follows that they must sometimes do so for reasons other than
those they themselves suggest.
Aspects versus Causes
The
CBTs, along with other cognitive approaches in psychology, often present their
understanding of psychopathology in a ‘box and arrow’ format. The arrows are
intended to represent causal relations; the boxes represent what are intended
to be understood as isolable cognitive, behavioural or emotional factors. Such
schematic models are appealing because they are clear-cut and appear to offer a
cogent rationale for investigation and intervention. Consider the following
highly condensed summaries of typical cognitive models:
One aspect of contemporary CBT models of panic can
be elaborated as follows: A patient experiences a bodily sensation. They
catastrophically misinterpret this as a sign of danger (e.g. that they are
fainting or having a heart attack). This leads to a further perception of
threat, giving rise to further fear, which in turn gives rise to further
sensations that are in turn catastrophically misinterpreted. The patient is
left in a rapidly cycling self-fuelling anxiety state (cf. Clark 1986).
The
depressed patient as encountered by the CBT therapist is an individual with
underlying pessimistic assumptions that organise his or her experience of the
world. When activated by critical incidents these assumptions are thought to
lead to the development of negative automatic thoughts (e.g. gloomy and
non-deliberative thoughts about the current situation, self or future). These
then give rise to negative emotions (e.g. guilt or fear), a lowering in mood,
and consequently to a reduction in motivation and activity and engagement. A
vicious circle of depressed thoughts and depressed mood results (cf. Beck,
1979; Fennell, 1989).
The patient with social anxiety often carries underlying
assumptions (e.g. ‘unless someone shows they like me, they dislike me’). The
CBT model describes how these can be activated in social situations, resulting
in a belief that they are in ‘social danger’ (e.g. believing that others will
treat me badly). Such beliefs may then cause anxiety, which in turn can cause
various somatic and cognitive symptoms (sweating, mind going blank, shaking).
These in turn can heighten a self-conscious mode of attention in which the
patient considers that they are, for example, likely to make fools out of
themselves (cf. Clark & Wells, 1995).
Models
such as these are, I find, often very useful in clinical practice since they
clearly depict what may be the main meanings and maintaining factors in the
various difficulties with which patients present, and immediately suggest
strategies for intervention. My objection at this stage, however, is not to
their clinical or heuristic utility, but to an aspect of their implicit
theorisation of the mind. The objection is that they tend to encourage us to
mistake a fact about our representations of the mind for a fact about what is
represented. The fact about our representations is that we can separately depict various aspects of
(say) a depressive state, such as our behavioural dispositions, thoughts,
motivation, mood, affects, etc. My claim here is that this cannot by itself be
taken to indicate a fact about what is represented: that there are separately existing assumptions and
perceptions and moods and motivational states – states ‘in us’, as we can
hardly now but put it – linked by causal connections (the arrows in the
diagrams).
Take the
case of panic. The CBT model separates out a stimulus, a perception of it as
threatening, a state of apprehension, and bodily sensations, and places these
separated phenomena into a causal sequence. Yet whilst all these ingredients
are clearly present in a panic attack, and whilst we can separate them for
formal (descriptive) purposes, it is not obvious that they really are, in the
normal run of things, best conceived of as separate states within a person
which causally trigger one another. A better description of them may
accordingly be as different aspects
of the same (anxiety) state. We are ‘stirred up’ – in both our action-readiness
and in a somatosensory way – by fearful stimuli, and our being stirred up in
this way is itself of a piece with
our registering of that stimulus as fearful. The components of our fear
response are, I submit, not isolable causally related states in us, but rather are merely notionally separable aspects of the state which we are in.
Much the
same can be said about the CBT conceptions of depression and social anxiety
outlined above. Something of the passive and objectifying voice of depressive
anxiety sometimes appears to have found its way in to the CBT conceptualisation
of the nature of our mental life per se.
Thus we now have assumptions that can be ‘activated’; meanings become reified
into occurrent processes and states to be known as ‘cognitions’; the agent
become a locus of ‘behaviours’. Everywhere we have to do with nouns, and
nowhere with verbs: to do with nouns that bolster an appearance that we are
referring to multiple isolable entities and processes, rather than with their
root verbs that refer to the action and attitude of a single living entity. The
living agent who makes assumptions, understands his experience a particular
way, and undertakes actions becomes instead a locus of separate inner and outer
states which causally trigger one another.
CBT
models can be useful as heuristics for thinking about psychopathology, and when
they do outline genuine causal interactions (two genuinely causal interactions
in the above models include fear and bodily sensations in panic, and inactivity
and depressed mood in depression) they significantly help to guide therapy.
Furthermore, their use of mechanistic and objectivising rhetoric which reduces
diverse (causal, dispositional, constitutive, etc.) relations to causal
relations is not in itself a mortal sin; the CBT theorist is after all not
pretending to provide us with a nuanced metaphysics or phenomenology of mind.
The criticism at this juncture is more modest. First, that certain cognitive
models have the somewhat misleading appearance of providing more by way of a
scientific psychological explanation than is really available. Relatedly they
can appear to possess a greater degree of scientific precision than found in
other models of therapy – although this appearance may be due only to their
having misleadingly dressed up description of different aspects of the
patient’s disturbance as a causal-explanatory model of it. Third that, because
of this, they can seem to overstate the number of apparent junctures for
intervention. But to summarise: as often as not, what such models are really
describing are different aspects of the same state we are in, rather than
describing scientifically teased out, causally linked, interruptible, states
and processes within us.
Thinking versus Having Thoughts
Whilst
all CBT theorists adhere to the centrality of cognition in emotional disturbance, not all theorists appear to
agree on the meaning of the term, a term that in any case is most often left
undefined. As described in the introduction, for some the term appears to refer
to any aspect of psychological performance (e.g. in perception, action,
emotion, judgement, etc.) that involves the conscious or preconscious processing or discrimination of meaning.
Under consideration may be enduring attitudes – dispositions of thought,
feeling and behaviour which may become sedimented in character – or passing
emotions, perceptions, cogitations, imaginings, and behaviours. For others,
including the founding fathers of CBT, the term refers more exclusively to our thinking, which in itself is understood
as realised in the words and images that pass across our minds. Such thinking
is conceived of as the second or third tier of a hierarchy of cognitive
elements which move from the most subconscious and dispositional (the underlying
schemata) level, through to more readily avowable maladaptive beliefs, up to
occurrent automatic thoughts passing across the mind. What follows concerns
only the latter sense of cognition (as occurrent thoughts passing across the
mind), and draws in part on the thoughtful critique of McEachrane (2009).
Here are
some examples of the idea that the content of (in traditional CBT), or the
patient’s fused relationship with (in ‘third-wave’ CBTs such as Acceptance and
Commitment Therapy or ‘ACT’), inner representational events maintains and
mediates emotional disturbance:
CBT therapists encourage [patients] to become aware of
their thoughts and thought processes. Cognitions are generally classified into
negative automatic thoughts and dysfunctional or irrational beliefs. Negative
automatic thoughts are thoughts or images that occur in specific situations
when an individual feels threatened in some way. (Hoffman & Asmundson,
2008, p. 4)
When a person is able to fill in the gap between an
activating event and the emotional consequences, the puzzling reaction becomes
understandable. With training, people are able to catch the rapid thoughts or
images that occur between an event and an emotional response. (Beck, 1979, p.
26)
ACT aims to alter the context in which thoughts occur so
as to decrease the impact and importance of difficult private events. ...
Clinically we want to teach clients to see thoughts as thoughts, feelings as
feelings, memories as memories, and physical sensations as physical sensations.
None of these private events are inherently toxic to human welfare when
experienced for what they are. (Hayes et al, 2004, p. 8)
[In] cognitive fusion … the event and ones thinking about
it become so fused as to be inseparable and that creates the impression that
verbal construal is not present at all. ... A worry about the future is
seemingly about the actual future, not merely an immediate process of
construing the future. The thought "Life is not worth living" is
seemingly a conclusion about life and its quality, not a verbal evaluative
process going on now. (Hayes et al, 2004, p. 25)
In these
examples we see clearly an idea that crops up not infrequently in the CBT
literature: that to think something is to have a thought pass across one’s
mind. We are, it is said, often oblivious to such inner events even occurring,
perhaps (in the case of ACT) because we are over-identified or ‘fused’ with
them. The therapist’s job is accordingly to help us notice and either challenge
(CBT) or defuse from (ACT) these events that supposedly mediate between outer
events and our feelings (on which more in the third section below). But as McEachrane (2009, p. 86)
suggests, ‘to say of someone that they ‘thought that p’ does not imply that they ‘thought of p’ or ‘thought about p’ or
formulated p or that p occurred to them or was in their thoughts. … [If] a
client says that in a particular situation they thought that, say, ‘I’ll never
be like them’ or … ‘I’m not a likeable person’, then this does not necessarily
mean that the client in that situation thought of these things, formulated these things to herself, that these
things occurred to her or were in her thoughts.’ If you ask me what I think
about the economic situation I need not wait on inner mental events to occur
which I can then report. Instead I simply tell you how the situation seems to
me, and in this telling I express what we could call my ‘attitudes’ rather than
report on my occurrent ‘cogitations’.
It is
important to be clear about the scope of this criticism. It is the aim of both
CBT and other therapies to help the patient to take a more ‘ironic’ and
flexible stance towards their own attitudes (Lear, 2003). Psychodynamic
therapies, for example, aim to help a patient develop in their ‘mentalising’,
to become aware that theirs is one among many possible ways of thinking about
things, and to increase their mental playfulness or psychological flexibility
(Holmes, 2009). Further, it is true that the depressed person can indeed become
ruminatively lost in an inner world of depressed and depressing cogitations; in
this case talk of ‘thoughts’ can indeed often be taken as talk of inner musings
or imagery. Helping the patient become aware that this is going on, and
encouraging them to instead harness their attentional resources to, make living
meanings in, and increase their physical engagement with, the external world
are well known to be therapeutically valuable. But treating everyday thoughts
as if they are typically inner events
not only falsifies the patient’s phenomenology, leading to possible ruptures in
the therapeutic alliance, but also risks alienating the subject from their own
attitudes.
This can
in particular be seen with respect to the above-reported thoughts described by
Hayes et al. (‘A worry about the future is seemingly about the actual future,
not merely an immediate process of construing the future. The thought
"Life is not worth living" is seemingly a conclusion about life and
its quality, not a verbal evaluative process going on now.’) You ask me: ‘Why
are you troubled?’ and I say ‘I’m worried about being made redundant, and the
possible effect of this on my family life.’ Whilst it may indeed be possible
for me to be overly worried and lose perspective, it is not at all clear that
this is best described as a matter of fusion with ‘immediate processes of
construing’ or with ‘verbal evaluative processes going on now’. By contrast
with what Hayes suggests, we can and indeed should say that a thought that life
is not worth living is indeed a judgment about life and its quality, regardless
of whether the judgement is expressed in inner speech; and we also can and
indeed should say that a worry about the future is indeed about the future,
regardless of whether it manifests in an episode of worrying.
This
difficulty does not adhere only to the third-wave CBTs such as Hayes’ ACT, but
attends to any therapy which encourages the patient to change what he thinks
(his attitudes) through changing his relation to or the content of his thinking
(his cogitations). For what is surely natural is to suppose that our
cogitations are often enough a function of our attitudes and not, on the whole,
vice versa. If, that is, my attitude is that my life is not worth living then,
when I am invited to attend only to my own cogitation I shall most likely be
attending to it – say to my occurrent thought of ‘this is all hopeless’ – from
just this attitude. In such a case my challenging of or distancing myself from
cogitations that reflect my attitudes risks becoming a strategy promoting bad faith
or self-alienation.
To
summarise: the CBTs invite the patient to notice their thoughts when they occur
and then to question them or otherwise get some distance from them. However the
thoughts often reported on thought records or in therapy sessions are
frequently best understood as attitudes that obtain, rather than as cogitations
that occur. They are of the substance of the person who thinks them, rather
than being entrancing inner events taking place in their minds to which they
stand in some kind of relation. So we need to bear in mind that to question
such thoughts is to question the patient himself. That is certainly a desirable
goal of therapy, but it will be obvious that it is a far more challenging goal
than one of simply helping the depressed patient to notice and question or
suspend his involvement in his mental processes. The latter task can be readily
conceived as a partly didactic and partly collaborative process; the former
more delicate task however will involve first forging a strong alliance with
the healthier part of the patient, bolstering their sense of themselves as
worthwhile and capable, so that the possibility can even arise of
disidentifying with their critical or demoralising inner voice.
It is
important not to overstate the case. What we will often find, especially in
depression, are certain depressogenic cogitations (‘ruminations’, ‘negative
automatic thoughts’) that have become habitual and fail to reflect the
underlying attitudes of the subject’s better self. This in fact is something
specific about depression rather than a function of having a mind per se. In
such cases learning to take a step back from rumination will of course be
important.[1]
Furthermore, therapists of all stripes will naturally want to help the patient
shift their underlying depressogenic attitudes, and not merely help shift the
depressive cogitations that stem from them.[2]
A point about the phenomenology of depression must be separated from one about
the logical grammar of ‘thought’: whilst rumination may well promote depressive
mood in depressed patients, this must be evidenced on empirical grounds, and
not simply follow from an a priori
misconstrual of all thought as cogitation. It is however just such a
misconstrual that sometimes finds its way into the CBT literature. As quoted
above, Hoffman & Asmundson (2008, p. 4) tell us that ‘CBT therapists
encourage [patients] to become aware of their thoughts and thought processes.
Cognitions are generally classified into negative automatic thoughts and dysfunctional
or irrational beliefs. Negative automatic thoughts are thoughts or images that
occur in specific situations when an individual feels threatened in some way.’
Yet often when we feel threatened in some way - for example when in a social
situation I think ‘they will reject me’ – this involves little or nothing by
way of anything like a negative automatic thought passing across my mind, and
instead concerns how I see the social situation I am in. To invite the patient
to record the thoughts which occur to them (say in a CBT ‘thought record’),
when the kind of thoughts that are at issue are not occurrent cogitations but
rather how they take matters to be, is to risk a misalliance through a
counter-therapeutic falsification of their phenomenology.
Feeling and Believing
Perhaps
the central claim of much CBT is that disturbances of emotion arise from
disturbances of cognition. This is often presented as a modern day form of the
stoic principle that ‘men are disturbed, not by things, but by the principles
and notions which they form concerning things’ (Epictetus, 2004, section V;
Robertson, 2010). As discussed in the introduction, much will turn on the
question of whether we are to understand cognition as i) referencing any
meaningful uptake or information processing of ‘things’ (in which case all
(non-behaviourist) psychotherapies including psychoanalysis must, in this
sense, be counted as cognitive therapies), or ii) whether we are to understand
it as referring instead to cognitive items such as acts of interpretation, the
application or formation of ‘principles and notions’, or to those of our
attitudes which are most aptly described as ‘underlying beliefs’. In this
section I shall consider ii) this more restricted latter sense of cognition,
and ask whether emotional disturbance is aptly theorized as consequent upon it.
Within
the CBT’s it is the ‘ABC’ model of emotional disorder, imported from Albert
Ellis’s Rational Emotive Behaviour Therapy (Ellis, 1991; Wilson & Branch,
2005), that most explicitly embodies the notion of cognitions as thoughts or
beliefs. ‘A’ here stands for the activating
events or situations experienced; ‘Bs’ are the subject’s beliefs about or interpretations of these events; ‘Cs’ are the
emotional or behavioural consequences.
The ABC model accordingly construes the cognitive state of belief as a
determining intermediary between experience and emotional response. The
viability of conceiving of the ‘C’ in CBT along the lines of the ‘B’ in ABC has
been questioned by CBT theorists on both theoretical and empirical grounds
(Kohlenberg & Tsai, 1994; Teasdale, 1997; Rachman, 1997). One rather
obvious empirical objection to the stoic claim that we are affected not by
things but by our interpretation of them comes from medical and conditioning approaches
to anxiety: I can be made mildly anxious directly by very strong coffee (even if
I mistakenly believe it to be decaffeinated); I may be directly emotionally
affected by hormonal changes or head injuries; I may feel compelled to perform
compulsions to reduce obsessional anxiety even whilst knowing there is no
rational basis for this; and I can be afraid of stimuli, such as spiders or
birds, which I believe to be perfectly safe (Whiting, 2006, p. 239) – hence the
relevance of behavioural therapies for certain phobic or compulsive behaviours.
Another objection comes from the observation that, whilst certain thoughts and
beliefs may be depressogenic or anxiogenic, this may only occur for people who
are already caught up in a particular frame of mind, perhaps driven by certain
unconscious desires and emotions (Whiting, 2006, p. 241). This, in fact, is an
objection anticipated by a key founder of CBT, Aaron Beck, who claimed only to
identify the maintaining factors, and not the underlying causes, of depression (Beck
et al., 1979; Clark & Steer, 1996). The question to be answered in this
chapter, however, concerns whether there are distinctly philosophical grounds
for questioning the idea that disturbed emotions are typically driven by
beliefs. My claim below is that the notion that this is so can sometimes be
seen to arise from a misunderstanding, inscribed in certain CBT theories, of
what it means to be an emotionally reactive human subject.
A
standard cognitive model of depression has it that aversive early experience
can lead to the formation of dysfunctional assumptions which, when activated by
a critical incident, lead to cycles of negative automatic thoughts and other
behavioural, motivational, affective, cognitive and somatic symptoms (Fennell,
1989, p. 171). These assumptions or beliefs are said to take such forms as ‘If
someone thinks badly of me, I cannot be happy’, or ‘I must do well at
everything I undertake’, ‘I am inferior as a person’, ‘My worth depends on what
other people think of me’ (Fennell, 1989, pp. 171-8). Therapy then consists in
strategies such as teaching the patient to become aware of depressing thoughts
as they occur, or undertaking tasks to test the truth of fixed negative beliefs
(Williams, 1997, p. 265). The first thing to be said about such propositions is
that, whilst the therapist probing for core beliefs
may well elicit them, they are often far more naturally taken to express a
patient’s feelings. McEachrane (2009, p. 92) quotes Ellis (1994, pp.
32-3) attempting to convince a patient of the opposite of this:
‘... I know I’m doing better of
course, and I’m sure it’s because of what’s gone on here in these sessions. And
I’m pleased and grateful to you. But I still feel basically the same way – that
there’s something really rotten about me, something I can’t do anything about,
and that the others are able to see. And I don’t know what to do about this
feeling.’
‘But this “feeling”, as you
call it, is largely your belief – do you see that?’
‘How can my feeling be a
belief? I really – uh – feel it. That’s all I can describe it as, a
feeling?’
‘Yes, but you feel it because
you believe it. If you believed, for example, really believed you were a
fine person, in spite of all the mistakes you have made and may still make in
life, and in spite of anyone else, such as your parents, thinking that you were
not so fine; if you really believed this, would you then feel
fundamentally rotten?’
‘Oh, Hmm. No, I guess you’re
right; I guess I then wouldn’t feel that way.’
However
the logical error here seems to be Ellis’s rather than his patient’s. Ellis
appears to be assuming that, since I am unlikely to feel rotten about myself if
I truly believe I am a good and fine person, then it must be the case that my
feeling rotten about myself is a product of my believing myself to be rotten.
But what, we might ask, if we start with the idea that beliefs are often
products of feelings rather than vice versa: might we not expect to arrive at
the same state of affairs? That is to say: if I felt – really felt – good about myself then may I not, as a consequence,
be disposed to form only positive beliefs about myself? And then might it not
also be true that sometimes people feel that there is something rotten about themselves
without having formed any associated belief – just as, say, a phobic person may
find herself feeling scared of spiders or birds without believing that they are
in any way dangerous? It may be hard to imagine truly believing that one is a
fine person whilst also feeling one is rotten, but this may reflect nothing
more than the powerfully constraining impact of feelings on belief formation.
Furthermore there may be many cases in which feeling and belief are
indistinguishable. Certain patients may defend against their painful emotions
by couching their self-talk in non-affective idioms (sticking to ‘believe’,
‘think’ etc.), but this shouldn’t lead us to overlook the sometimes genuinely
interchangeable roles that ‘feel’ and ‘believe’ may occupy. We should also not
forget those uses of ‘feel’ which function precisely to draw a contrast with
‘believe’ or ‘know’: ‘I feel lucky today – although I don’t believe in luck’;
‘I know that you were in the right but I still feel hurt’.
One way
in which a CBT theorist might try to salvage the idea that it is maladaptive
beliefs that drive emotional disturbance could be as follows. Beliefs, they may
say, possess intentionality and carry mental content (they are about this or that). Feelings, on the
other hand, are merely ‘positive’ or ‘negative’ (‘hot’ or ‘cold’) emotions,
sensations, or states of being. Feelings therefore need to be driven by beliefs
before they can properly be said to be about anything or to express any kind of
understanding. The reply to this is that it is hard to understand why we should
accept such an impoverished conception of our feelings. For feelings often
precisely are about something: I feel furious that he has wasted my time; she is sad because he has left without saying goodbye; he is delighted by her having accepted his proposal. And
since our feelings are very naturally taken to be already about states of
affairs, it is hard to see what help they need from intermediary beliefs.
Imagine
that I always dreamed of being a psychologist but then fail my exams and become
morose. This emotional state of mine worsens and I start to believe that I
cannot be happy unless I am a psychologist. A CBT therapist who becomes wedded
to the idea that intermediary beliefs or adherence to rules underpins emotional
distress may propose that it is precisely this belief of mine that is driving
my despondency. It is indeed possible that such additional beliefs may serve to
maintain or worsen depression. What isn’t clear though is why much of my
sadness may not be thought of as arising simply because I have not realized my
life’s ambition. What is significant here is not an intervening belief about what I need to be happy,
but more generally how I see my life,
my outlook on or evaluative perception of my self, my situation and my future (cf.
McEachrane, 2009, pp. 94-5). In a depressive frame of mind I may arrive at
beliefs such as ‘I cannot be happy unless I am a psychologist’, but such
beliefs are, I suggest, in the run of things more likely to result from my
sense of my situation rather than vice versa.
What
then are we to make of the not infrequent CBT insistence that beliefs have a
key pathogenic role to play in depression and other emotional disorders? My own
belief is that, whilst certain CBT therapists may sometimes be driven by an
overly intellectual (belief- or rule-mediated) conception of our emotional
perception of our worlds, what has more often happened is that they have
stretched the meaning of ‘belief’ to fit the phenomenology and save the theory.
For example, I once asked my then CBT supervisor what she meant by her talk of
her patients’ ‘beliefs’, and she replied that you knew that what you had to do
with was a belief when a patient cries in articulating it. This clearly has
little to do with the normal notion of belief, given that the infinity of our
everyday beliefs (that it is not raining, that most people have legs, that the
next symbol is a closing parenthesis…) hardly provokes an infinity of tears.
What instead we have to do with here may rather be the result of a common
enough situation in psychiatry and psychotherapy generally: that the practical
meanings of clinical terms become constituted more by their actual clinical
uses than by associated theory, where such clinical uses are themselves a
product of a distinctive lexicon being forced to carry whatever are the communicative and therapeutic burdens of the
clinical encounter.
This
explanation should not, of course, be mistaken for an exculpation. CBT theorists
have as much a professional duty to communicate clearly and accurately as all psychologists,
and misusing ordinary terms (‘belief’, ‘thought’) may be no less unhelpful than
deploying the language of science when it adds nothing to what is better stated
in everyday language.[3] And the fact
remains that we do ordinarily distinguish between beliefs and feelings, and use
the distinction to mark situations in which, say, we feel scared of a cat even
whilst believing it to be safe. Furthermore cognitive neuroscience has now
provided several models outlining different streams of ‘information processing’
for propositional and embodied understandings (cf Power & Dalgleish, 1999;
Teasdale, 1997). Rather than think of the emotionally significant meanings
which arise as a patient experiences their world as encoded in propositionally
structured interpretations or beliefs, such theorists instead invite us to
consider the prime significance of non-linguistic, somatosensory, forms of
meaning. The clinical upshot is that therapy must aim at helping a patient
change their way of being in the world through changing such non-belief-based
meanings.
In this
section I have added to such empirical critique by providing philosophical
reasons for thinking that an ‘ABC’-style model falsifies what it actually means
to be an emotionally reactive, meaning sensitive, human subject. If, when a CBT theorist tells us that
emotional reactions are shaped by our ‘cognitions’ they mean by ‘cognitions’
something like our beliefs, and if by
our ‘beliefs’ they mean something other than how we feel about or see our situations, then the CBT theorist appears to run the risk of radically
misconstruing the foundations of our affectivity by putting the cart of our
belief before the horse of our emotion.
On Articulating Our Assumptions
In this
section I inquire into the relation between i) a patient’s verbal articulations
in therapy of their underlying self-understandings, and ii) the nature of such
underlying self-understandings. Several typical CBT models expound something
like the following: i) that the first, rather preliminary, step of cognitive
therapy is to help the patient clearly identify
their emotionally problematic core beliefs, rules and assumptions. And ii) that
the second task is to encourage them to quasi-scientifically test out these assumptions, either
through rational engagement (e.g. Kuehlwein, 2002) leading to what is sometimes
called ‘cognitive restructuring’, or more practically through ‘behavioural
experiments’ (e.g. Bennett-Levy, 2004).
In what
follows I will challenge such a conception of what is happening in therapy when
assumptions are articulated, questioned or put to the test. My aim is not to
question the CBT practice, but rather to question the conception of
self-understanding that it encourages: that articulation of one’s own
self-understanding in therapy is a rather preliminary stage occurring prior to
the genuine transformations that can occur only when such self-understandings
are challenged and healthier alternatives considered and embraced. The
criticism offered here will be that those CBTs operating according to the above
description risk underplaying both i) the transformative nature of the
acknowledgement of one’s deepest fears, and ii) the way in which verbal,
behavioural and experiential therapeutic techniques function not merely to test
hypotheses, but rather to effect a more fundamental change in the form of the
patient’s thought. A more fundamental change, that is, that first of all
enables it to become penetrable by the light that experience and rational
enquiry can shine into the fearful recesses of the mind.
Consider
first what happens when an underlying dysfunctional assumption gets put into
words, perhaps through the application of the ‘downward arrow’ technique. (This
technique has the therapist repeatedly ask of, say, a patient voicing
self-critical thoughts, questions such as ‘and if that were true, what would
that say about you?’ until a definitive underlying negative fear is
articulated.) Here is how Fennell (1989, pp. 204-5) articulates the therapeutic
strategy:
Rather than challenging the
thoughts themselves, the therapist asks: ‘Supposing that was true, what would
that mean about you?’ This and similar questions… are repeated until it is
possible to formulate a statement general enough to encompass not only the
original problem-situation, but also other situations where the same rule is
operating. … Once a dysfunctional assumption has been identified, questioning
and behavioural experimentation are used to find a new, more moderate and
realistic rule.
Fennell’s
own assumption is that dysfunctional assumptions can be hard to unearth
because, ‘rather than [being] discrete events occurring in consciousness, they
are generalized rules which may never have been formulated in so many words’
(1989, p. 204). Why such assumptions should not have been put into words is not
considered by her, nor is the emotional experience of the patient who
articulates them - which, in my clinical experience at least, typically
involves a quite particular mixture of distress and relief.[4]
This empirical issue is not however our key concern here – which is instead
philosophical and concerns what happens to
such tacit assumptions when they are voiced. Fennell’s presentation, which is
quite standard in the CBT literature, encourages the view that their voicing involves
merely their being put into words. But reflection on what is meant by the
voicing of our deepest troubling thoughts – reflection that is philosophical in
so far as it concerns itself with how the objects of psychological
investigation ought to be characterised, rather than itself depending on the
results of empirical enquiry – reveals something richer. The articulation of
one’s previously unarticulated fears involves, that is, not merely voicing but
also acknowledgement, a correlative increase in self-understanding, an emancipation which comes from making
visible or thinkable those assumptions which otherwise continue to invisibly
constrain our meaningful experience and, so long as the resultant fears can be
contained until they dissipate, an increased
capacity to tolerate reality.
To take
up the last of these: the patient who presents under the influence of a
dysfunctional assumption which they have not yet articulated to themselves can
often be seen to be failing to fully distinguish between fear (or wish) and
belief. Whether they always really believe,
for example, that others laugh at them as they walk down the street, or whether
this is simply what they fearfully imagine
or think, is not always entirely clear. An important reason for this is
that they can be presenting in a state of mind which somewhat ablates the very
distinction between fearing and believing.[5]
Their ‘safety behaviours’ (which they perform to prevent (what they imagine
will be) the experienced realisation of their fears – e.g. never meeting the
gaze of others for fear of meeting a hostile look, or never failing to grip
onto the shopping trolley for fear that they would collapse) similarly keep in
place the constitutive lack of clarity of the anxious state. However when the
CBT therapist encourages them to test out their fears by surveying the beliefs
of others, or by undertaking a behavioural experiment (which may involve seeing
if matters really do deteriorate if they don’t perform their safety
behaviours), what happens is not merely that the truth of an assumption is
evaluated, but that a clear distinction between fear and genuine belief begins
to be instated in the mind. A fearful state of mind that demotes reality
contact becomes substituted for by an empirical hypothesis.
Or perhaps
the patient is invited to put a probability figure to their fear: what is the
actual likelihood that you will be scoffed at if you show your face in the town
centre? 90%? 20%? Once again the CBT strategy invites the transformation of
what would once have been called a ‘neurotic’ state (in which an avoidance of
reality has conspired with and inspired a fusion of fear, belief and experience
– a state which may sometimes be compensated for by structurally similar
fusions of wish, belief and experience) into an empirical hypothesis. Various
CBT strategies have the clarifying effect of helping the patient shape up their
fearful state so that it can be brought into contact with reality, first expressing
it in the necessary bivalent (true/false) or probabilistic form of a genuinely
reality-oriented proposition. They have this effect, that is, despite perhaps understanding
themselves as merely being in the business of promoting the voicing then the
testing of beliefs. What is significant here is not so much the disproving, but
the shift that occurs within the structure of such fears when they are rendered
provable or disprovable.
In this
section I have suggested that whether we are dealing with the verbal
articulation, or with the testing, of a patient’s deepest dysfunctional
assumptions, what is principally significant is a change in the form of the
patient’s fears. For what renders such assumptions dysfunctional is not simply
their content but also their neurotic form – their insulation from empirical
testing and rational thought, their fusion with wish or fear – and it is a
change in such form which ultimately makes for the possibility of a change in
unhelpful content. The CBT therapist’s armoury of tools for unearthing and
engaging with such assumptions has the effect of shining the light of reason
into the darker recesses of the patient’s mind, encouraging their thought to be
governed not by fearful fancy but rather by what psychoanalysts would call ‘the
reality principle’. In the process their thought becomes articulated – which is
to say, not merely voiced but structured so that it now more clearly embeds a
distinction between appearance and reality, is less insulated from reality
testing, and is less a hostage of their deepest fears and wishes.
A much
debated concern in the scientific CBT literature is whether the benefits of CBT
are mediated by cognitive changes in the patient, whether such benefits may
occur before cognitive techniques have even been applied, and whether cognitive
techniques really add much to behavioural therapy (Longmore & Worrell,
2007). One way of putting the philosophical point I am making here is that
expressive and behavioural techniques can already be seen to be (in the
broadest sense) cognitive – in so far as they involve a change in the form of
the patient’s fearful or depressive cognitions (cf. Carey & Mansell, 2009).
The various techniques of CBT serve to free the patient from those inchoate
fears that hitherto have not found adequate, clearly delineated, expression.
Making the fears less inchoate and more thinkable risks making them feel more
real, and the avoidance of this scary possibility often seems to have been a
significant part of the patient’s difficulties. Therapy, however, provides an
emotionally ‘containing’ environment in which the therapist’s clarity regarding
the relatively benign and possibly even nourishing nature of social reality –
by contrast with what the patient fearfully imagines to be the case – can
become internalised by the patient. It is for this reason that a good
therapeutic relationship must not merely be collaborative (Leahy, 2008) but
also be emotionally containing, and an effective CBT therapist’s containing
manner shows itself in her confidence in the empirical methods of CBT, her
pragmatism, clarity, reality orientation, compassion and warmth.
Conclusion
To
summarise the above four objections: the first proposed that certain CBT
formulations conflate internal relations of meaning with causal relations
between discrete inner states, resulting in models of psychopathology that
appear more scientific than they really are. The second had it that some CBT
models construed emotionally laden perspectives too much as an occurrent inner
process, and too little as a subject’s attitudes. The third considered that
such attitudes can sometimes be misdescribed in CBT models as beliefs – when
what we really have to do with here are feelings with intrinsic meanings. The
fourth argued that CBT models can underplay the significance of changes in the
form of (a subject’s ownership of) such attitudes when they focus instead on
changing their content. In these concluding paragraphs I will consider whether
these various distortions to what it means to be a living human subject can be
understood as aspects of a single common tendency of thought to which the CBTs
may at times be prey.
My
suggestion here is that what unifies the above disturbances of vision is their
being expressive of what could be called an ‘alienated’ conception of human
subjectivity. I will now spell out what I mean by this. Imagine that the self
were no longer an expressive bodily being located immanently by its feelings
within an already meaningful intersubjective world – but had retreated inwards,
away from the world, the body, and even the mind, becoming instead a disengaged
inner spectator trying to make sense from the outside of a world onto which it
looks. Perhaps such a self is a prototype of a scientist-observer who is in the
business of trying to control and predict the world by constructing inner
representations or interpretations of it.[6]
The effects of such a retreated conception of the self would be several. The
mind and body, having been denuded of subjectivity,
will now more naturally appear as domains of merely causally (rather than
meaningfully) inter-related, objectified
states and processes. Models of psychopathology constructed within such a
vision start to look as if they possess some kind of scientific edge, since the description of the inner life of their
subjects seems to provide an account of a scientifically describable network of
causally inter-related isolable states and processes – rather than a phenomenological description of how we
manifest and are embedded in our intentional worlds. The self will no longer
speak from its attitudes, but will
rather be reduced to speaking about
them. Our minds and bodies become not so much what we could call the flesh
or substance of the self, but instead show up as domains of inner and outer
processes that are in interaction with
the self. Therapy, accordingly, would get seen as no longer in the business
of self-transformation, but instead
becomes a technology – grounded in what will appear to be, amongst the
therapies, uniquely scientific causal models of inter-related inner processes –
for helping us manage our minds. Our
relationships too will be reduced to a merely external form – which is to say,
that they will become not constitutive of
who we are, but rather seen merely to
causally connect us to that which is essentially other. So too the being of
the patient will no longer be thought of as partly immanent in the emotional flux of the therapeutic relationship;
that relationship will instead risk being reduced to something which is merely
a collaboration between distinct
relata.
Precisely
such a mechanistic and self-alienated conception of the mind can, it seems to
me, be what we often find in the patient who presents wanting to know how to
better ‘control their anxiety’, ‘change their thoughts’ or ‘manage their feelings’.
Such a patient has, we could say, become alienated from their own inner life
which, accordingly, is seen as an independent domain painfully afflicting them
and requiring management or excision. Now it bears recollection that in this
chapter I have not been concerned to critique CBT per se, but instead to
scrutinise some of the ways in which some models of some CBTs may sometimes be
inflected in ways that go against what it means to be an emotionally alive
human subject. The risk for the CBTs that I have identified could be described
as one of joining the above-described patient in such a de-subjectivised vision
of the psyche. By way of corrective what we can remember is that by helping the
patient to give articulate structure to his fears, to think, to be nourished by
reality contact, and to distinguish fearful fantasy from genuinely
representational belief, the CBT practitioner can be understood as doing far
more than, say, helping her patient to test out his hypotheses; she is helping
to restore her patient’s subjectivity.
References
Beck, AT
1976, Cognitive therapy and the emotional
disorders, Meridian Press, New York.
Beck,
AT, Rush AJ, Shaw, BG & Emery, G 1979, Cognitive
therapy of depression, Guilford, New York.
Bennett-Levy,
J, Butler, G, Fennell, M, Hackmann, A, Mueller, M & Westbrook, D 2004, Oxford guide to behavioural experiments in
cognitive therapy, Oxford University Press.
Carey, TA & Mansell, W 2009, ‘Show us a behaviour without a cognition and
we'll show you a rock rolling down a hill’, The Cognitive Behaviour Therapist, vol. 2, pp. 123-133.
Clark,
DM & Steer, RA 1996, ‘Empirical status of the cognitive model of anxiety
and depression’, in Salkovskis, PM (ed.), Frontiers
of cognitive therapy, The Guilford Press, New York, pp. 75-96.
Robertson,
D 2010, The philosophy of cognitive behavioural
therapy (CBT): Stoic philosophy as rational and cognitive psychotherapy,
Karnac Books, London.
Clark,
DM 1989, ‘Anxiety states: panic and generalized anxiety’, in Hawton, K, Salkovskis,
P, Kirk, J & Clark, D (eds.) Cognitive behaviour therapy for psychiatric
problems: a practical guide,
Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Ellis, A
1991, ‘The revised ABC’s of rational-emotive therapy (RET)’, Journal of
Rational
Emotive
and Cognitive Behavior Therapy, vol. 9, no. 3, pp. 139-172.
Epictetus
2004, Enchiridion. Dover.
Hayes, S,
Strosahl, K, Bunting, K, Twohig, M & Wilson, K 2004, ‘What is Acceptance
and Commitment Therapy?’, in Hayes, S & Strosahl, K (eds.) A practical guide to Acceptance and
Commitment Therapy, Springer, New York.
Holmes,
J 2009, Exploring in security: towards an
attachment-informed psychoanalytic psychotherapy, Routledge, Hove.
Kelly, G
1955, The psychology of personal
constructs, W. W. Norton & Co., New York.
Kohlenberg,
RJ & Tsai, M 1994, ‘Improving cognitive therapy for depression with
functional analytic psychotherapy: theory and case study’, The Behavior Analyst, vol. 17, pp. 305-319.
Kuehlwein,
KT 2002, ‘The cognitive treatment of depression’, in Simos, G (ed.) Cognitive
behaviour therapy: a guide for the practising clinician, Brunner-Routledge,
Hove.
Leahy, R
2008, ‘The therapeutic relationship in cognitive-behavioural therapy’, Behavioural and Cognitive Psychotherapy,
vol. 36, pp. 769-777.
Lear, J
2003, Therapeutic action: an earnest plea for irony, Other Press, New
York.
McEachrane,
M 2009, ‘Capturing emotional thoughts: the philosophy of cognitive-behavioral therapy’,
in Gustafsson, Y, Kronqvist, C & McEachrane, M (eds.) Emotions and understanding:
Wittgensteinian perspectives. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke.
Newman,
MG & Borkovec, TD 2002, ‘Cognitive behavioural therapy for worry and
generalised anxiety disorder’, in Simos, G (ed.) Cognitive behaviour
therapy: a guide for the practising clinician, Brunner-Routledge, Hove.
Mollon,
P 2007, ‘Debunking the ‘pseudoscience’ debunkers’,
Clinical Psychology Forum, vol. 174, pp.
13-16.
Power,
MJ & Dalgleish, T 1999, ‘Two routes to emotion: some implications of
multi-level theories of emotion for therapeutic practice’, Behavioural and Cognitive Psychotherapy, vol. 27, pp. 129-141.
Robertson,
D 2010, The philosophy of cognitive-behavioural
therapy (CBT): Stoic philosophy as rational and cognitive psychotherapy,
Karnac Books, London.
Teasdale,
J 1997, ‘The relationship between cognition and emotion: the mind-in-place in
mood disorders’, in Clark, D & Fairburn, C (eds.), Science and practice of cognitive behaviour therapy, Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Wilson,
R & Branch, R 2005, Cognitive behavioural
therapy for dummies, John Wiley & Sons, Chichester.
Whittal,
M, Rachman, S & McLean, P 2002, ‘Psychosocial treatment for OCD: combining
cognitive and behavioural treatments’, in Simos, G (ed.) Cognitive behaviour
therapy: a guide for the practising clinician, Brunner-Routledge, Hove.
[1] What it
takes to effect such learning remains a matter of contention. Psychodynamic
therapists suggest that the patient develops such mental space through
internalising the therapeutic relationship; they suggest that the high relapse
rates after short-term therapy for depression reflect a failure of such
internalisation. CBT therapists, by contrast, typically conceive of a
collaborative therapeutic relationship as merely facilitative of intrinsically
non-relational learning of good inductive habits, and suggest that relapses are
due to a failure of such learning.
[2] How
these attitudes are to be conceived – as beliefs (as the CBT theorist often
conceives them) or as feelings (as the psychodynamic therapist often suggests)
– will be considered in the next section.
[3] For example
Mollon (2007, p. 13) complains of the scientistic rhetoric of the CBT
literature, where ‘facing your fears is called ‘exposure’, refraining from an
activity is called ‘response prevention’, learning to relax is called ‘stress
inoculation’, and revising your thoughts is called ‘cognitive restructuring’’.
[4] The
psychodynamic theorist has a ready explanation of such phenomenology: that the
articulation of such assumptions involves the lifting of the repression of
emotionally painful material.
[6] George
Kelly, psychologist of ‘personal constructs’, proposed just such a
scientist-observer conception of the human subject (Kelly, 1955). His work
significantly influenced the early CBT theorist Albert Ellis.
Comments
Post a Comment
Comment here!